User:Boris Tsirelson/Sandbox2

From Knowino
Jump to: navigation, search

In probability theory, a standard probability space (called also Lebesgue–Rokhlin probability space or just Lebesgue space; the latter term is ambiguous) is a probability space satisfying certain assumptions introduced by Vladimir Rokhlin in 1940. He showed that the unit interval endowed with the Lebesgue measure has important advantages over general probability spaces, and can be used as a probability space for all practical purposes in probability theory. The theory of standard probability spaces was started by von Neumann in 1932 and shaped by Vladimir Rokhlin in 1940. The dimension of the unit interval is not a concern, which was clear already to Norbert Wiener. He constructed the Wiener process (also called Brownian motion) in the form of a measurable map from the unit interval to the space of continuous functions.

Contents

[edit] Short history

The theory of standard probability spaces was started by von Neumann in 1932[1] and shaped by Vladimir Rokhlin in 1940.[2] For modernized presentations see (Haezendonck 1973), (de la Rue 1993), (Itô 1984, Sect. 2.4) and (Rudolf 1990, Chapter 2).

Nowadays standard probability spaces may be (and often are) treated in the framework of descriptive set theory, via standard Borel spaces, see for example (Kechris 1995, Sect. 17). This approach, natural for experts in descriptive set theory, is based on the isomorphism theorem for standard Borel spaces (Kechris 1995, Theorem (15.6)) whose proof is very difficult for non-experts in descriptive set theory. The original approach of Rokhlin, based on measure theory, leads to much simpler proofs (since measure theory may neglect null sets, in contrast to descriptive set theory).

Standard probability spaces are used routinely in ergodic theory,[3][4] which cannot be said on probability theory. Some probabilists hold the following opinion: only standard probability spaces are pertinent to probability theory, thus, it is a pity that the standardness is not included into the definition of probability space. Others disagree, however.

Arguments against standardness:

Arguments in favour of standardness:

[edit] Definition

One of several well-known equivalent definitions of the standardness is given below, after some preparations. All probability spaces are assumed to be complete.

[edit] Isomorphism

An isomorphism between two probability spaces \textstyle (\Omega_1,\mathcal{F}_1,P_1) , \textstyle (\Omega_2,\mathcal{F}_2,P_2) is an invertible map \textstyle f : \Omega_1 \to \Omega_2 such that \textstyle f and \textstyle f^{-1} both are (measurable and) measure preserving maps.

Two probability spaces are isomorphic, if there exists an isomorphism between them.

[edit] Isomorphism modulo zero

Two probability spaces \textstyle (\Omega_1,\mathcal{F}_1,P_1) , \textstyle (\Omega_2,\mathcal{F}_2,P_2) are isomorphic \textstyle \operatorname{mod} \, 0 , if there exist null sets \textstyle A_1 \subset \Omega_1 , \textstyle A_2 \subset \Omega_2 such that the probability spaces \textstyle \Omega_1 \setminus A_1 , \textstyle \Omega_2 \setminus A_2 are isomorphic (being endowed naturally with sigma-fields and probability measures).

[edit] Standard probability space

A probability space is standard, if it is isomorphic \textstyle \operatorname{mod} \, 0 to an interval with Lebesgue measure, a finite or countable set of atoms, or a combination (disjoint union) of both.

See (Rokhlin 1962, Sect. 2.4 (p. 20)), (Haezendonck 1973, Proposition 6 (p. 249) and Remark 2 (p. 250)), and (de la Rue 1993, Theorem 4-3). See also (Kechris 1995, Sect. 17.F), and (Itô 1984, especially Sect. 2.4 and Exercise 3.1(v)). In (Petersen 1983, Definition 4.5 on page 16) the measure is assumed finite, not necessarily probabilistic. In (Sinai 1994, Definition 1 on page 16) atoms are not allowed.

[edit] Examples of non-standard probability spaces

[edit] A naive white noise

The space of all functions \textstyle f : \mathbb{R} \to \mathbb{R} may be thought of as the product \textstyle \mathbb{R}^\mathbb{R} of a continuum of copies of the real line \textstyle \mathbb{R} . One may endow \textstyle \mathbb{R} with a probability measure, say, the standard normal distribution \textstyle \gamma = N(0,1) , and treat the space of functions as the product \textstyle (\mathbb{R},\gamma)^\mathbb{R} of a continuum of identical probability spaces \textstyle (\mathbb{R},\gamma) . The product measure \textstyle \gamma^\mathbb{R} is a probability measure on \textstyle \mathbb{R}^\mathbb{R} . Many non-experts are inclined to believe that \textstyle \gamma^\mathbb{R} describes the so-called white noise.

However, it does not. For the white noise, its integral from 0 to 1 should be a random variable distributed N(0, 1). In contrast, the integral (from 0 to 1) of \textstyle f \in \textstyle (\mathbb{R},\gamma)^\mathbb{R} is undefined. Even worse, ƒ fails to be almost surely measurable. Still worse, the probability of ƒ being measurable is undefined. And the worst thing: if X is a random variable distributed (say) uniformly on (0, 1) and independent of ƒ, then ƒ(X) is not a random variable at all! (It lacks measurability.)

[edit] A perforated interval

Let \textstyle Z \subset (0,1) be a set whose inner Lebesgue measure is equal to 0, but outer Lebesgue measure – to 1 (thus, \textstyle Z is nonmeasurable to extreme). There exists a probability measure \textstyle m on \textstyle Z such that \textstyle m(Z \cap A) = \text{mes} (A) for every Lebesgue measurable \textstyle A \subset (0,1) . (Here \textstyle \text{mes} is the Lebesgue measure.) Events and random variables on the probability space \textstyle (Z,m) (treated \textstyle \operatorname{mod} \, 0 ) are in a natural one-to-one correspondence with events and random variables on the probability space \textstyle ((0,1),\text{mes}) . Many non-experts are inclined to conclude that the probability space \textstyle (Z,m) is as good as \textstyle ((0,1),\text{mes}) .

However, it is not. A random variable \textstyle X defined by \textstyle X(\omega)=\omega is distributed uniformly on \textstyle (0,1) . The conditional measure, given \textstyle X=x , is just a single atom (at \textstyle x), provided that \textstyle ((0,1),\text{mes}) is the underlying probability space. However, if \textstyle (Z,m) is used instead, then the conditional measure does not exist when \textstyle x \notin Z .

A perforated circle is constructed similarly. Its events and random variables are the same as on the usual circle. The group of rotations acts on them naturally. However, it fails to act on the perforated circle.

See also (Rudolph 1990, page 17).

[edit] A superfluous measurable set

Let \textstyle Z \subset (0,1) be as in the previous example. Sets of the form \textstyle ( A \cap Z ) \cup ( B \setminus Z ), where \textstyle A and \textstyle B are arbitrary Lebesgue measurable sets, are a σ-algebra \textstyle \mathcal{F}; it contains the Lebesgue σ-algebra and \textstyle Z. The formula

\displaystyle m \big( ( A \cap Z ) \cup ( B \setminus Z ) \big) = p \, \operatorname{mes} (A) + (1-p) \operatorname{mes} (B)

gives the general form of a probability measure \textstyle m on \textstyle \big( (0,1), \mathcal{F} \big) that extends the Lebesgue measure; here \textstyle p \in [0,1] is a parameter. To be specific, we choose \textstyle p = 0.5. Many non-experts are inclined to believe that such an extension of the Lebesgue measure is at least harmless.

However, it is the perforated interval in disguise. The map

\displaystyle f(x) = \begin{cases}
 0.5 x &\text{for } x \in Z, \\
 0.5 + 0.5 x &\text{for } x \in (0,1) \setminus Z
\end{cases}

is an isomorphism between \textstyle \big( (0,1), \mathcal{F}, m \big) and the perforated interval corresponding to the set

\displaystyle Z_1 = \{ 0.5 x : x \in Z \} \cup \{ 0.5 + 0.5 x : x \in (0,1) \setminus Z \} \, ,

another set of inner Lebesgue measure 0 but outer Lebesgue measure 1.

See also (Rudolph 1990, Exercise 2.11 on page 18).

[edit] A criterion of standardness

Standardness of a given probability space \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) is equivalent to a certain property of a measurable map \textstyle f from \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) to a measurable space \textstyle (X,\Sigma). Interestingly, the answer (standard, or not) does not depend on the choice of \textstyle (X,\Sigma) and \textstyle f . This fact is quite useful; one may adapt the choice of \textstyle (X,\Sigma) and \textstyle f to the given \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P). No need to examine all cases. It may be convenient to examine a random variable \textstyle f : \Omega \to \mathbb{R}, a random vector \textstyle f : \Omega \to \mathbb{R}^n, a random sequence \textstyle f : \Omega \to \mathbb{R}^\infty, or a sequence of events \textstyle (A_1,A_2,\dots) treates as a sequence of two-valued random variables, \textstyle f : \Omega \to \{0,1\}^\infty.

Two conditions will be imposed on \textstyle f (to be injective, and generating). Below it is assumed that such \textstyle f is given. The question of its existence will be addressed afterwards.

The probability space \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) is assumed to be complete (otherwise it cannot be standard).

[edit] A single random variable

A measurable function \textstyle f : \Omega \to \mathbb{R} induces a pushforward measure, --- the probability measure \textstyle \mu on \textstyle \mathbb{R}, defined by

\displaystyle \mu(B) = P \big( f^{-1}(B) \big)    for Borel sets \textstyle B \subset \mathbb{R}.

(It is nothing but the distribution of the random variable.) The image \textstyle f (\Omega) is always a set of full outer measure,

\displaystyle \mu^* \big( f(\Omega) \big) = 1,

but its inner measure can differ (see a perforated interval). In other words, \textstyle f (\Omega) need not be a set of full measure \textstyle \mu.

A measurable function \textstyle f : \Omega \to \mathbb{R} is called generating if \textstyle \mathcal{F} is the completion of the σ-algebra of inverse images \textstyle f^{-1}(B), where \textstyle B \subset \mathbb{R} runs over all Borel sets.

Caution.   The following condition is not sufficient for \textstyle f to be generating: for every \textstyle A \in \mathcal{F} there exists a Borel set \textstyle B \subset \mathbb{R} such that \textstyle P ( A \Delta f^{-1}(B) ) = 0. (\textstyle \Delta means symmetric difference).

Theorem. Let a measurable function \textstyle f : \Omega \to \mathbb{R} be injective and generating, then the following two conditions are equivalent:

See also (Itô 1984, Sect. 3.1).

[edit] A random vector

The same theorem holds for any  \mathbb{R}^n \, (in place of  \mathbb{R} \,). A measurable function  f : \Omega \to \mathbb{R}^n \, may be thought of as a finite sequence of random variables  X_1,\dots,X_n : \Omega \to \mathbb{R}, \, and  f \, is generating if and only if  \mathcal{F} \, is the completion of the σ-algebra generated by  X_1,\dots,X_n. \,

[edit] A random sequence

The theorem still holds for the space  \mathbb{R}^\infty \, of infinite sequences. A measurable function  f : \Omega \to \mathbb{R}^\infty \, may be thought of as an infinite sequence of random variables  X_1,X_2,\dots : \Omega \to \mathbb{R}, \, and  f \, is generating if and only if  \mathcal{F} \, is the completion of the σ-algebra generated by  X_1,X_2,\dots. \,

[edit] A sequence of events

In particular, if the random variables  X_n \, take on only two values 0 and 1, we deal with a measurable function  f : \Omega \to \{0,1\}^\infty \, and a sequence of sets  A_1,A_2,\ldots \in \mathcal{F}. \, The function  f \, is generating if and only if  \mathcal{F} \, is the completion of the σ-algebra generated by  A_1,A_2,\dots. \,

In the pioneering work (Rokhlin 1962) sequences  A_1,A_2,\ldots \, that correspond to injective, generating  f \, are called bases of the probability space  (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) \, (see Rokhlin 1962, Sect. 2.1). A basis is called complete mod 0, if  f(\Omega) \, is of full measure  \mu, \, see (Rokhlin 1962, Sect. 2.2). In the same section Rokhlin proved that if a probability space is complete mod 0 with respect to some basis, then it is complete mod 0 with respect to every other basis, and defines Lebesgue spaces by this completeness property. See also (Haezendonck 1973, Prop. 4 and Def. 7) and (Rudolph 1990, Sect. 2.3, especially Theorem 2.2).

[edit] Additional remarks

The four cases treated above are mutually equivalent, and can be united, since the measurable spaces  \mathbb{R}, \,  \mathbb{R}^n, \,  \mathbb{R}^\infty \, and  \{0,1\}^\infty \, are mutually isomorphic; they all are standard measurable spaces (in other words, standard Borel spaces).

Existence of an injective measurable function from \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) to a standard measurable space \textstyle (X,\Sigma) does not depend on the choice of \textstyle (X,\Sigma). Taking \textstyle (X,\Sigma) =  \{0,1\}^\infty we get the property well-known as being countably separated (but called separable in Itô 1984).

Existence of a generating measurable function from \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) to a standard measurable space \textstyle (X,\Sigma) also does not depend on the choice of \textstyle (X,\Sigma). Taking \textstyle (X,\Sigma) =  \{0,1\}^\infty we get the property well-known as being countably generated (mod 0), see (Durrett 1996, Exer. I.5).

Probability space Countably separated Countably generated Standard
Template:Rh | Interval with Lebesgue measure Symbol confirmed.svg Symbol confirmed.svg Symbol confirmed.svg
Template:Rh | Naive white noise Symbol unrelated.svg Symbol unrelated.svg Symbol unrelated.svg
Template:Rh | Perforated interval Symbol confirmed.svg Symbol confirmed.svg Symbol unrelated.svg

Every injective measurable function from a standard probability space to a standard measurable space is generating. See (Rokhlin 1962, Sect. 2.5), (Haezendonck 1973, Corollary 2 on page 253), (de la Rue 1993, Theorems 3-4, 3-5). This property does not hold for the non-standard probability space dealt with in the subsection "A superfluous measurable set" above.

Caution.   The property of being countably generated is invariant under mod 0 isomorphisms, but the property of being countably separated is not. In fact, a standard probability space \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) is countably separated if and only if the cardinality of \textstyle \Omega does not exceed continuum (see Itô 1984, Exer. 3.1(v)). A standard probability space may contain a null set of any cardinality, thus, it need not be countably separated. However, it always contains a countably separated subset of full measure.

[edit] Equivalent definitions

Let \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) be a complete probability space such that the cardinality of \textstyle \Omega does not exceed continuum (the general case is reduced to this special case, see the caution above).

[edit] Via absolute measurability

Definition.   \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) is standard if it is countably separated, countably generated, and absolutely measurable.

See (Rokhlin 1962, the end of Sect. 2.3) and (Haezendonck 1973, Remark 2 on page 248). "Absolutely measurable" means: measurable in every countably separated, countably generated probability space containing it.

[edit] Via perfectness

Definition.   \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) is standard if it is countably separated and perfect.

See (Itô 1984, Sect. 3.1). "Perfect" means that for every measurable function from \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) to  \mathbb{R} \, the image measure is regular. (Here the image measure is defined on all sets whose inverse images belong to \textstyle \mathcal{F} , irrespective of the Borel structure of  \mathbb{R} \,).

[edit] Via topology

Definition.   \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) is standard if there exists a topology \textstyle \tau on \textstyle \Omega such that

See (de la Rue 1993, Sect. 1).

[edit] Verifying the standardness

Every probability distribution on the space \textstyle \mathbb{R}^n turns it into a standard probability space. (Here, a probability distribution means a probability measure defined initially on the Borel sigma-algebra and completed.)

The same holds on every Polish space, see (Rokhlin 1962, Sect. 2.7 (p. 24)), (Haezendonck 1973, Example 1 (p. 248)), (de la Rue 1993, Theorem 2-3), and (Itô 1984, Theorem 2.4.1).

For example, the Wiener measure turns the Polish space \textstyle C[0,\infty) (of all continuous functions \textstyle [0,\infty) \to \mathbb{R}, endowed with the topology of local uniform convergence) into a standard probability space.

Another example: for every sequence of random variables, their joint distribution turns the Polish space \textstyle \mathbb{R}^\infty (of sequences; endowed with the product topology) into a standard probability space.

(Thus, the idea of dimension, very natural for topological spaces, is utterly inappropriate for standard probability spaces.)

The product of two standard probability spaces is a standard probability space.

The same holds for the product of countably many spaces, see (Rokhlin 1962, Sect. 3.4), (Haezendonck 1973, Proposition 12), and (Itô 1984, Theorem 2.4.3).

A measurable subset of a standard probability space is a standard probability space. It is assumed that the set is not a null set, and is endowed with the conditional measure. See (Rokhlin 1962, Sect. 2.3 (p. 14)) and (Haezendonck 1973, Proposition 5).

Every probability measure on a standard Borel space turns it into a standard probability space.

[edit] Using the standardness

[edit] Regular conditional probabilities

In the discrete setup, the conditional probability is another probability measure, and the conditional expectation may be treated as the (usual) expectation with respect to the conditional measure, see conditional expectation. In the non-discrete setup, conditioning is often treated indirectly, since the condition may have probability 0, see conditional expectation. As a result, a number of well-known facts have special 'conditional' counterparts. For example: linearity of the expectation; Jensen's inequality (see conditional expectation); Hölder's inequality; the monotone convergence theorem, etc.

Given a random variable \textstyle Y on a probability space \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) , it is natural to try constructing a conditional measure \textstyle P_y , that is, the conditional distribution of \textstyle \omega \in \Omega given \textstyle Y(\omega)=y . In general this is impossible (see Durrett 1996, Sect. 4.1(c)). However, for a standard probability space \textstyle (\Omega,\mathcal{F},P) this is possible, and well-known as canonical system of measures (see Rokhlin 1962, Sect. 3.1), which is basically the same as conditional probability measures (see Itô 1984, Sect. 3.5), disintegration of measure (see Kechris 1995, Exercise (17.35)), and regular conditional probabilities (see Durrett 1996, Sect. 4.1(c)).

The conditional Jensen's inequality is just the (usual) Jensen's inequality applied to the conditional measure. The same holds for many other facts.

[edit] Measure preserving transformations

Given two probability spaces \textstyle (\Omega_1,\mathcal{F}_1,P_1) , \textstyle (\Omega_2,\mathcal{F}_2,P_2) and a measure preserving map \textstyle f : \Omega_1 \to \Omega_2 , the image \textstyle f(\Omega_1) need not cover the whole \textstyle    \Omega_2 , it may miss a null set. It may seem that \textstyle P_2(f(\Omega_1)) has to be equal to 1, but it is not so. The outer measure of \textstyle f(\Omega_1) is equal to 1, but the inner measure may differ. However, if the probability spaces \textstyle (\Omega_1,\mathcal{F}_1,P_1) , \textstyle (\Omega_2,\mathcal{F}_2,P_2) are standard then \textstyle P_2(f(\Omega_1))=1 , see (de la Rue 1993, Theorem 3-2). If \textstyle f is also one-to-one then every \textstyle A \in \mathcal{F}_1 satisfies \textstyle f(A) \in \mathcal{F}_2 , \textstyle P_2(f(A))=P_1(A) . Therefore \textstyle f^{-1} is measurable (and measure preserving). See (Rokhlin 1962, Sect. 2.5 (p. 20)) and (de la Rue 1993, Theorem 3-5). See also (Haezendonck 1973, Proposition 9 (and Remark after it)).

"There is a coherent way to ignore the sets of measure 0 in a measure space" (Petersen 1983, page 15). Striving to get rid of null sets, mathematicians often use equivalence classes of measurable sets or functions. Equivalence classes of measurable subsets of a probability space form a normed complete Boolean algebra called the measure algebra (or metric structure). Every measure preserving map \textstyle f : \Omega_1 \to \Omega_2 leads to a homomorphism \textstyle F of measure algebras; basically, \textstyle F(B) = f^{-1}(B) for \textstyle B\in\mathcal{F}_2 .

It may seem that every homomorphism of measure algebras has to correspond to some measure preserving map, but it is not so. However, for standard probability spaces each \textstyle F corresponds to some \textstyle f . See (Rokhlin 1962, Sect. 2.6 (p. 23) and 3.2), (Kechris 1995, Sect. 17.F), (Petersen 1983, Theorem 4.7 on page 17).

[edit] Notes

  1. (von Neumann 1932) and (Halmos & von Neumann 1942) are cited in (Rokhlin 1962, page 2) and (Petersen 1983, page 17).
  2. Published in short in 1947, in detail in 1949 in Russian and in 1952 in English, reprinted in 1962 (Rokhlin 1962). An unpublished text of 1940 is mentioned in (Rokhlin 1962, page 2). "The theory of Lebesgue spaces in its present form was constructed by V. A. Rokhlin" (Sinai 1994, page 16).
  3. "In this book we will deal exclusively with Lebesgue spaces" (Petersen 1983, page 17).
  4. "Ergodic theory on Lebesgue spaces" is the subtitle of the book (Rudolph 1990).

[edit] References

.

Category:Probability theory Category:Measure theory

Personal tools
Namespaces
Variants
Actions
Navigation
Community
Toolbox